Open Always
Email: support@globalcompose.com Call Now! +1-315 515-4588
Open Always
Email: support@globalcompose.com Call Now! +1-315 515-4588

Case Study Assignment on Consumers and Business Ethics

Assignment Writing Help

This assignment question was recently posted by one of our customers and shared with our professional writers. If you are looking for assignment help on this topic or similar topic, click on ORDER NOW button to submit your details. Once we have your order details, your assignment will be assigned to one of our best writers, who will then proceed to write your paper and deliver it within your specified deadline. Thank you for choosing us today!

Case Study Assignment on Consumers and Business Ethics

Reading6.1, “The Ethics of Sales”

Do businesses and their employees have an obligation to treat their consumers ethically? More specifically, do salespeople have an ethical obligation to provide their customers with the information they need to make mutually beneficial purchases?

 Learning Goal:To further your understanding of ethical issues relating to business sales and marketing by critically analyzing a debate over which moral principles should regulate businessconsumer interactions.

 write an essay that critically analyzes “The Ethics of Sales,” by Thomas Carson (Case 6.1 in the textbook, pp. 306-313). 3. In your essay, you should pick between the two theories of the ethics of sale put forth by Carson and David Holley, and then explain why the theory you picked is better justified than the alternative.

 What is the difference between lying and deception? According to Carson, does withholding information constitute deception? What about concealing information? (b) What is the principle of caveat emptor? What is merchantability?

 Holly writes that salespeople are required to avoid undermining the conditions of acceptable exchange. What three conditions are necessary for an “acceptable exchange”?

Assess the three criticisms that Carson makes of Holley’s theory. Do you find them persuasive? (e) According to Carson, what four duties do salespeople have? Explain how the Golden Rule supports these duties. Is Carson’s interpretation of the Golden Rule the best way of understanding it? In your view, is the Golden Rule a basic principle of ethics? Explain why or why not. What implications does the Golden Rule have for salespeople? (f) Do Carson’s duties 1 through 4 provide a more plausible account of the ethics of sales than Holly’s theory does? Explain why or why not. Do you agree that the actions in examples A, B, and C are morally wrong?

 

 

Reading 6.1: The Ethics of Sales

Thomas L. Carson

In this essay, Thomas L. Carson, professor of philosophy at Loyola University of Chicago, examines the moral obligations of salespeople. After explaining and criticizing David Holley’s well-known account of the ethics of sales, Carson puts forward his own theory, which identifies four moral duties of salespeople. Carson contends that his theory provides intuitively plausible results in concrete cases, that it avoids the weaknesses of Holley’s approach, and that it explains why different kinds of salespeople have different kinds of duties to their customers. He goes on to argue that the most plausible version of the Golden Rule supports his theory. He concludes by discussing several examples that illustrate and clarify his theory.

Sales

The ethics of sales is an important, but neglected, topic in business ethics. Approximately 10 percent of the U.S. work force is involved in sales. In addition, most of us occasionally sell major holdings such as used cars and real estate. Because sales were long governed by the principle of caveat emptor, discussions of the ethics of sales usually focus on the ethics of withholding information and the question “What sort of information is a salesperson obligated to reveal to customers?” One of the best treatments of this topic is David Holley’s paper “A Moral Evaluation of Sales Practices.” In this essay, I explain Holley’s theory, propose several criticisms, and formulate what I take to be a more plausible theory about the duties of salespeople. My theory avoids the objections I raise against Holley and yields intuitively plausible results when applied to cases. I also defend my theory by appeal to the golden rule and offer a defense of the version of the golden rule to which I appeal.

Preliminaries: A Conceptual Roadmap

We need to distinguish between lying, deception, withholding information, and concealing information. Roughly, deception is intentionally causing someone to have false beliefs. Standard dictionary definitions of lying say that a lie is a false statement intended to deceive others. The Oxford English Dictionary (1989) defines a lie as: “a false statement made with the intent to deceive.” Webster’s (1963) gives the following definition of the verb lie: “to make an untrue statement with intent to deceive.” … Lies that don’t succeed in causing others to have false beliefs are not instances of deception. The word deception implies success in causing others to have false beliefs, but lying is often unsuccessful in causing deception. A further difference between lying and deception is that, while a lie must be a false statement, deception needn’t involve false statements; true statements can be deceptive and many forms of deception do not involve making statements of any sort. Thus, many instances of deception do not constitute lying. Withholding information does not constitute deception. It is not a case of causing someone to have false beliefs; it is merely a case of failing to correct false beliefs or incomplete information. On the other hand, actively concealing information usually constitutes deception.

The Common Law Principle of Caveat Emptor

According to the common law principle of caveat emptor, sellers are not required to inform prospective buyers about the properties of the goods they sell. Under caveat emptor, sales and contracts to sell are legally enforceable even if the seller fails to inform the buyer of serious defects in the goods that are sold. Buyers themselves are responsible for determining the quality of the goods they purchase. In addition, English common law sometimes called for the enforcement of sales in cases in which sellers made false or misleading statements about the goods they sold (Atiyah 464–65).

Currently, all U.S. states operate under the Uniform Commercial Code of 1968. Section 2-313 of the code defines the notion of sellers’ warranties (Preston 52). The code provides that all factual affirmations or statements about the goods being sold are warranties. This means that sales are not valid or legally enforceable if the seller makes false statements about the goods s/he is selling. The American legal system has developed the concept of an “implied” (as opposed to an express or explicit) warranty. Implied warranties are a significant limitation on the principle of caveat emptor. According to the Uniform Commercial Code, any transaction carries with it the following implied warranties:

  • (1) that the seller owns the goods he is selling and
  • (2) that the goods are “merchantable,” i.e., suitable for the purposes for which they are sold (Preston 56–57).

Many local ordinances require that people who sell real estate inform buyers about all known serious defects of the property they sell. These ordinances are also a significant limitation on the traditional principle of caveat emptor.

Deceptive sales practices also fall under the purview of the Federal Trade Commission (FTC). The FTC prohibits deceptive sales practices—practices likely to materially mislead reasonable consumers (FTC Statement 1983).

Many salespeople take complying with the law to be an acceptable moral standard for their conduct and claim that they have no moral duty to provide buyers with information about the goods they sell, except for that information which the law requires for an enforceable sale.

Holley’s Theory

Holley’s theory is based on his concept of a “voluntary” or “mutually beneficial” market exchange (Holley uses the terms voluntary exchange and mutually beneficial exchange interchangeably). He says that a voluntary exchange occurs “only if” the following conditions are met (Holley takes his conditions to be necessary conditions for an acceptable exchange):

  1. Both buyer and seller understand what they are giving up and what they are receiving in return.
  2. Neither buyer nor seller is compelled to enter into the exchange as a result of coercion, severely restricted alternatives, or other constraints on the ability to choose.
  3. Both buyer and seller are able at the time of the exchange to make rational judgments about its costs and benefits (Holley 463).

These three conditions admit of degrees of satisfaction. An ideal exchange is an exchange involving people who are fully informed, fully rational, and “enter into the exchange entirely of their own volition” (Holley 464). The conditions for an ideal exchange are seldom, if ever, met in practice. However, Holley claims that it is still possible to have an “acceptable exchange” if the parties are “adequately informed, rational, and free from compulsion.”

According to Holley, “the primary duty of salespeople to customers is to avoid undermining the conditions of an acceptable exchange.” He makes it clear that, on his view, acts of omission (as well as acts of commission) can undermine the conditions of an acceptable exchange (Holley 464).

Because of the complexity of many goods and services, customers often lack information necessary for an acceptable exchange. Careful examination of products will not necessarily reveal problems or defects. According to Holley, caveat emptor is not acceptable as a moral principle, because customers often lack information necessary for an acceptable exchange. In such cases, salespeople are morally obligated to give information to the buyer. The question then is: What kind of information do salespeople need to provide buyers in order to ensure that the buyer is adequately informed? Holley attempts to answer this question in the following passage in which he appeals to the golden rule:

Determining exactly how much information needs to be provided is not always clear-cut. We must in general rely on our assessments of what a reasonable person would want to know. As a practical guide, a salesperson might consider, “What would I want to know, if I were considering buying this product?” (Holley 467)

This principle is very demanding, perhaps more demanding than Holley realizes. Presumably, most reasonable people would want to know a great deal about the things they are thinking of buying. They might want to know everything relevant to the decision whether or not to buy something (more on this point shortly).

Criticisms of Holley

First, when time does not permit it, a salesperson cannot be morally obligated to provide all information necessary to ensure that the customer is adequately informed (all the information that a reasonable person would want to know if she were in the buyer’s position). In many cases, reasonable customers would want to know a great deal of information. Often salespeople simply don’t have the time to give all customers all the information Holley deems necessary for an acceptable exchange. Salespeople don’t always know all the information that the buyer needs for an acceptable exchange. It cannot be a person’s duty to do what is impossible—the statement that someone ought to do a certain act implies that she can do that act. Further, in many cases, salespeople don’t know enough about the buyer’s state of knowledge to know what information the buyer needs in order to be adequately informed. A salesperson might know that the buyer needs certain information in order to be adequately informed but not know whether or not the buyer possesses that information. One might reply that salespeople should know all the information necessary for an adequate exchange. However, on examination, this is not a plausible view. A salesperson in a large retail store cannot be expected to be knowledgeable about every product he sells. Often, it is impossible for realtors and used car salesmen to know much about the condition of the houses and cars they sell or the likelihood that they will need expensive repairs.

Second, Holley’s theory implies that a salesperson in a store would be obligated to inform customers that a particular piece of merchandise in her store sells for less at a competing store if she knows this to be the case. (Presumably, she would want to know where she can get it for the lowest price, were she herself considering buying the product.) Not only do salespeople have no duty to provide this kind of information, (ordinarily) it would be wrong for them to do so.

Third, Holley’s theory seems to yield unacceptable consequences in cases in which the buyer’s alternatives are severely constrained. Suppose that a person with a very modest income attempts to buy a house in a small town. Her options are severely constrained, since there is only one house for sale in her price range. According to Holley, there can’t be an acceptable exchange in such cases, because condition number 2 is not satisfied. However, it’s not clear what he thinks sellers ought to do in such cases. The seller can’t be expected to remove these constraints by giving the buyer money or building more homes in town. Holley’s view seems to imply that it would be wrong for anyone to sell or rent housing to such a person. This result is unacceptable.

Toward a More Plausible Theory About the Ethics of Sales

I believe that salespeople have the following moral duties regarding the disclosure of information when dealing with rational adult consumers (cases involving children or adults who are not fully rational raise special problems that I will not try to deal with here):

  1. Salespeople should provide buyers with safety warnings and precautions about the goods they sell. (Sometimes it is enough for salespeople to call attention to written warnings and precautions that come with the goods and services in question. These warnings are unnecessary if the buyers already understand the dangers or precautions in question.)
  2. Salespeople should refrain from lying and deception in their dealings with customers.
  3. As much as their knowledge and time constraints permit, salespeople should fully answer questions about the products and services they sell. They should answer questions forthrightly and not evade questions or withhold information that has been asked for (even if this makes it less likely that they will make a successful sale). Salespeople are obligated to answer questions about the goods and services they sell. However, they are justified in refusing to answer questions that would require them to reveal information about what their competitors are selling. They are not obligated to answer questions about competing goods and services or give information about other sellers.
  4. Salespeople should not try to “steer” customers toward purchases that they have reason to think will prove to be harmful to customers (financial harm counts) or that customers will come to regret.

These are prima facie duties that can conflict with other duties and are sometimes overridden by other duties. A prima facie duty is one’s actual duty, other things being equal; it is an actual duty in the absence of conflicting duties of greater or equal importance. For example, my prima facie duty to keep promises is my actual duty in the absence of conflicting duties of equal or greater importance. The above is a minimal list of the duties of salespeople concerning the disclosure of information. I believe that the following are also prima facie duties of salespeople, but I am much less certain that these principles can be justified:

  1. Salespeople should not sell customers goods or services they have reason to think will prove to be harmful to customers or that the customers will come to regret later, without giving the customers their reasons for thinking that this is the case. (This duty does not hold if the seller has good reasons to think that the customer already possesses the information in question.)
  2. Salespeople should not sell items they know to be defective or of poor quality without alerting customers to this. (This duty does not hold if the buyer can be reasonably expected to know about the poor quality of what he is buying.)

I have what I take to be strong arguments for 1–4, but I’m not so sure that I can justify 5 and 6. I believe that reasonable people can disagree about 5 and 6. (I have very little to say about 5 and 6 in the present essay. See Carson [2001] for a discussion of arguments for 5 and 6.)

There are some important connections between duties 2, 4, and 6. Lying and deception in sales are not confined to lying to or deceiving customers about the goods one sells. Many salespeople misrepresent their own motives to customers/clients. Almost all salespeople invite the trust of customers/clients and claim, implicitly or explicitly, to be acting in the interests of customers/clients. Salespeople often ask customers to defer to their judgment about what is best for them. For most salespeople, gaining the trust of customers or clients is essential for success. Many salespeople are not interested in helping customers in the way they represent themselves as being. A salesperson who misrepresents her motives and intentions to customers violates rule 2. This simultaneous inviting and betrayal of trust is a kind of treachery. In ordinary cases, rules against lying and deception alone prohibit salespeople from steering customers toward goods or services they have reason to think will be bad for them. It is difficult to steer someone in this way without lying or deception, e.g., saying that you believe that a certain product is best for someone when you don’t believe this to be the case. Similar remarks apply to selling defective goods. Often, it is impossible to do this without lying to or deceiving customers. In practice, most or many violations of rules 4 and 6 are also violations of rule 2.

A Justification for My Theory

Rules 1–4 yield intuitively plausible results in concrete cases and avoid all of the objections I raised against Holley. They can also be justified by appeal to the golden rule.

Taken together, rules 1–4 give us an intuitively plausible theory about the duties of salespeople regarding the disclosure of information; they give more acceptable results in actual cases than Holley’s theory. They can account for cases in which the conduct of salespeople seems clearly wrong, e.g., cases of lying, deception, and steering customers into harmful decisions. Unlike Holley’s theory, rules 1–4 do not make unreasonable demands on salespeople. They don’t require that salespeople provide information that they don’t have or spend more time with customers than they can spend. Nor do they require salespeople to divulge information about the virtues of what their competitors are selling.

In addition, my theory explains why different kinds of salespeople have different kinds of duties to their customers. For example, ordinarily, realtors have a duty to provide much more information to customers than sales clerks who sell inexpensive items in gift stores. My theory explains this difference in terms of the following:

  1. the realtor’s greater knowledge and expertise;
  2. the much greater amount of time the realtor can devote to the customer;
  3. the greater importance of the purchase of a home than the purchase of a small gift and the greater potential for harm or benefit to the buyer; and (in some cases)
  4. implicit or explicit claims by the realtor to be acting on behalf of prospective home buyers (clerks in stores rarely make such claims).

The Golden Rule

I think that the golden rule is most plausibly construed as a consistency principle (those who violate the golden rule are guilty of inconsistency). The following version of the golden rule can be justified.

GR: Consistency requires that if you think that it would be morally permissible for someone to do a certain act to another person, then you must consent to someone else doing the same act to you in relevantly similar circumstances.

How the Golden Rule Supports My Theory

Given this version of the golden rule, any rational and consistent moral judge who makes judgments about the moral obligations of salespeople will have to accept rules 1–4 as prima facie duties. Consider each duty in turn:

  1. All of us have reason to fear the hazards about us in the world; we depend on others to warn us of those hazards. Few people would survive to adulthood were it not for the warnings of others about such things as oncoming cars, live electric wires, and approaching tornadoes. No one who values her own life can honestly say that she is willing to have others fail to warn her of dangers.
  2. Like everyone else, a salesperson needs correct information in order to act effectively to achieve her goals and advance her interests. She is not willing to act on the basis of false beliefs. Consequently, she is not willing to have others deceive her or lie to her about matters relevant to her decisions in the marketplace. She is not willing to have members of other professions (such as law and medicine) make it a policy to deceive her or lie to her whenever they can gain financially from doing so.
  3. Salespeople have questions about the goods and services they themselves buy. They can’t say that they are willing to have others evade or refuse to answer those questions. We want our questions to be answered by salespeople or else we wouldn’t ask them. We are not willing to have salespeople evade or refrain from answering our questions. (Digression: Rule 3 permits salespeople to refuse to answer questions that would force them to provide information about their competitors. Why should we say this? Why not say instead that salespeople are obligated to answer all questions that customers ask? The answer is as follows: A salesperson’s actions affect both her customers and her employer. In applying the golden rule to this issue she can’t simply ask what kind of information she would want were she in the customer’s position [Holley poses the question in just this way]. Rule 3 can probably be improved upon, but it is a decent first approximation. A disinterested person who was not trying to give preference to the interests of salespeople, employers, or customers could endorse 3 as a policy for salespeople to follow. We can and must recognize the legitimacy of employers’ demands for loyalty. The role of being an advocate or agent for someone who is selling things is legitimate within certain bounds—almost all of us are willing to have real estate agents work for us. A rational person could consent to the idea that everyone follows principles such as rule 3.)
  4. All of us are capable of being manipulated by others into doing things that harm us, especially in cases in which others are more knowledgeable than we are. No one can consent to the idea that other people (or salespeople) should manipulate us into doing things that harm us whenever doing so is to their own advantage. Salespeople who claim that it would be permissible for them to make it a policy to deceive customers, fail to warn them about dangers, evade their questions, or manipulate them into doing things that are harmful to them whenever doing so is advantageous to them are inconsistent because they are not willing to have others do the same to them. They must allow that 1–4 are prima facie moral duties.

Rules 1–4 are only prima facie duties. The golden rule can account for the cases in which 1–4 are overridden by other more important duties. For example, we would be willing to have other people violate rules 1–4 if doing so were necessary in order to save the life of an innocent person. In practice, violating 1, 2, 3, or 4 is permissible only in very rare cases. The financial interests of salespeople seldom justify violations of 1, 2, 3, or 4. The fact that a salesperson can make more money by violating 1, 2, 3, or 4 would not justify her in violating any of these unless she has very pressing financial obligations that she cannot meet otherwise. Often, salespeople need to meet certain minimum sales quotas to avoid being fired. Suppose that a salesperson needs to make it a policy to violate 1–4 in order to meet her sales quotas and keep her job. Would this justify her in violating 1–4? Possibly. But, in order for this to be the case, the following conditions would have to be met: (a) she has important moral obligations such as feeding and housing her family that require her to be employed (needing money to keep one’s family in an expensive house or take them to Disney World wouldn’t justify violating 1–4); and (b) she can’t find another job that would enable her to meet her obligations without violating 1–4 (or other equally important duties). Those salespeople who can’t keep their jobs or make an adequate income without violating 1–4 should seek other lines of employment.

A Defense of the Version of the Golden Rule Employed Earlier

My argument is as follows:

  1. Consistency requires that if you think that it would be morally permissible for someone to do a certain act to another person, then you must grant that it would be morally permissible for someone to do that same act to you in relevantly similar circumstances.
  2. Consistency requires that if you think that it would be morally permissible for someone to do a certain act to you in certain circumstances, then you must consent to him/her doing that act to you in those circumstances.

Therefore,

GR: Consistency requires that if you think that it would be morally permissible for someone to do a certain act to another person, then you must consent (not object to) someone doing the same act to you in relevantly similar circumstances. (You are inconsistent if you think that it would be morally permissible for someone to do a certain act to another person, but do not consent to someone doing the same act to you in relevantly similar circumstances.)

This argument is valid, i.e., the conclusion follows from the premises, and both its premises are true. Both premises are consistency requirements. Premise 1 addresses questions about the consistency of a person’s different moral beliefs. Premise 2 addresses questions about whether a person’s moral beliefs are consistent with her attitudes and actions. Our attitudes and actions can be either consistent or inconsistent with the moral judgments we accept.

Premise 1

Premise 1 follows from, or is a narrower version of, the universalizability principle (UP). The UP can be stated as follows:

Consistency requires that, if one makes a moral judgment about a particular case, then one must make the same moral judgment about any similar case, unless there is a morally relevant difference between the cases.

Premise 1 is a principle of consistency for judgments about the moral permissibility of actions. The UP, by contrast, is a principle of consistency for any kind of moral judgment, including judgments about what things are good and bad.

Premise 2

How shall we understand what is meant by “consenting to” something? For our present purposes, we should not take consenting to something to be the same as desiring it or trying to bring it about. My thinking that it is morally permissible for you to beat me at chess does not commit me to desiring that you beat me, nor does it commit me to playing so as to allow you to beat me. Consenting to an action is more like not objecting to it, not criticizing, or not resenting the other person for doing it. If I think that it is permissible for you to beat me at chess then I cannot object to your beating me. I am inconsistent if I object to your doing something that I take to be morally permissible. If I claim that it is permissible for someone to do something to another person, then, on pain of inconsistency, I cannot object if someone else does the same thing to me in relevantly similar circumstances. The gist of my application of the golden rule to sales is that since we do object to salespeople doing such things as lying to us, deceiving us, and failing to answer our questions, we cannot consistently say that it is morally permissible for them to do these things.

Examples

I will discuss several cases to illustrate and clarify my theory.

Example A

I am selling a used car that I know has bad brakes; this is one of the reasons I am selling the car. You don’t ask me any questions about the car, and I sell it to you without informing you of the problem with the brakes.

Example B

I am selling a used car that starts poorly in cold weather. You arrange to look at the car early in the morning on a very cold day. I don’t own a garage so the car is out in the cold. With difficulty, I start it up and drive it for thirty minutes shortly before you look at it and then cover the car with snow to make it seem as if it hasn’t been driven. The engine is still hot when you come and the car starts up immediately. You then purchase the car, remarking that you need a car that starts well in the cold to get to work, since you don’t have a garage.

Example C

While working as a salesperson, I feign a friendly concern for a customer’s interests. I say, “I will try to help you find the product that is best suited for your needs. I don’t want you to spend any more money than you need to. Take as much time as you need.” The customer believes me, but she is deceived. In fact, I couldn’t care less about her welfare. I only want to sell her the highest priced item I can as quickly as I can. I don’t like the customer; indeed, I am contemptuous of her.

In example A, I violate rule 1 and put the buyer and other motorists, passengers, and pedestrians at risk. In example B, I violate rules 2 and 5. In example C, I violate rule 2. In the absence of conflicting obligations that are at least as important as the rules I violate, my actions in cases A–C are morally wrong.

Example D: A Longer Case (an Actual Case)

In 1980, I received a one-year fellowship from The National Endowment for the Humanities. The fellowship paid for my salary, but not my fringe benefits. Someone in the benefits office of my university told me that I had the option of continuing my health insurance through the university if I paid for the premiums out of my own pocket. I told the benefits person that this was a lousy deal and that I could do better by going to a private insurance company. I went to the office of Prudential Insurance agent Mr. A. O. “Ed” Mokarem. I told him that I was looking for a one-year medical insurance policy to cover me during the period of the fellowship and that I planned to resume my university policy when I returned to teaching. (The university provided this policy free of charge to all faculty who were teaching.) He showed me a comparable Prudential policy that cost about half as much as the university’s policy. He explained the policy to me. I asked him to fill out the forms so that I could purchase the policy. He then told me that there was a potential problem I should consider. He said roughly the following:

You will want to return to your free university policy next year when you return to teaching. The Prudential policy is a one-year terminal policy. If you develop any serious medical problems during the next year, Prudential will probably consider you “uninsurable” and will not be willing to sell you health insurance in the future. If you buy the Prudential policy, you may encounter the same problems with your university policy. Since you will be dropping this policy voluntarily, they will have the right to underwrite your application for re-enrollment. If you develop a serious health problem during the next year, their underwriting decision could be “Total Rejection,” imposing some waivers and/or exclusions, or (at best) subjecting your coverage to the “pre-existing conditions clause,” which would not cover any pre-existing conditions until you have been covered under the new policy for at least a year.

If I left my current health insurance for a year, I risked developing a costly medical condition for which no one would be willing to insure me. That would have been a very foolish risk to take. So, I thanked him very much and, swallowing my pride, went back to renew my health insurance coverage through the university. I never bought any insurance from Mr. Mokarem and never had occasion to send him any business.

I have discussed this case with numerous classes through the years. It usually generates a lively discussion. Most of my students do not think that Mr. Mokarem was morally obligated to do what he did, but they don’t think that what he did was wrong either—they regard his actions as supererogatory or above and beyond the call of duty.

My View about Example D. On my theory, this is a difficult case to assess. If rules 1–4 are a salesperson’s only duties concerning the disclosure of information, then Mr. Mokarem was not obligated to inform me as he did. (In this case, the information in question was information about a competing product—the university’s health insurance policy.) If rule 5 is a prima facie duty of salespeople, then (assuming that he had no conflicting moral duties of greater or equal importance) it was his duty, all things considered, to inform me as he did. Since I am uncertain that 5 can be justified, I’m not sure whether or not Mr. Mokarem was obligated to do what he did or whether his actions were supererogatory. This case illustrates part of what is at stake in the question of whether rule 5 is a prima facie duty of salespeople.

Acknowledgments

This essay is a revised and abridged version of material from two earlier essays, “Deception and Withholding Information in Sales,” Business Ethics Quarterly 11 (2001): 275–306, and “Ethical Issues in Selling and Advertising,” The Blackwell Guide to Business Ethics, ed. Norman Bowie (Oxford: Blackwell, 2002), 186–205. Many thanks to Ivan Preston for his very generous and helpful advice and criticisms. Everyone interested in these topics should read his work.

 

Academic Writing Help

All writing formats, 24/7 customer support via live chat, email or phone number, and timely delivery guaranteed.

Are you looking for homework writing help? Click on Order Now button below to Submit your assignment details.

Homework Writing Help
We Can Help you with this Assignment right now!

Are you looking for homework writing help on this topic? This question was posted by one of our client seeking homework help.  If you are therefore looking for an assignment to submit, then click on ORDER NOW button or contact us today. Our Professional Writers will be glad to write your paper from scratch, and delivered within your deadline. Perfect choice for your excellent grades! www.globalcompose.com.

 

We ensure that assignment instructions are followed, the paper is written from scratch. If you are not satisfied by our service, you can either request for refund or unlimited revisions for your order at absolutely no extra pay. Once the writer has completed your paper, the editors check your paper for any grammar/formatting/plagiarism mistakes, then the final paper is sent to your email.

Privacy| Confidentiality

We do not share your personal information with any company or person. We have also ensured that the ordering process is secure; you can check the security feature in the browser. For confidentiality purposes, all papers are sent to your personal email. If you have any questions, contact us any time via email, live chat or our phone number.

Our Clients Testimonials

  • I appreciate help on the assignment. It was hard for me but am good to go now

    Impact of pollution on Environment
  • Am happy now having completed the very difficult assignment

    Creative Message Strategies
  • Your writer did a fine job on the revisions. The paper is now ok

    Ethics: Theory and Practice
  • The paper was so involving but am happy it is done. Will reach you with more assignments

    Title: Privatization in or of America
  • I expected perfection in terms of grammar and I am happy. Lecturer is always on our head but was pleased with my paper. Once again, thanks a lot

    Title: Bundaberg Inquiry
  • The paper looks perfect now, thank to the writer

    Health Care Systems
  • You helped me complete several other tasks as you handled paper. wonna thank you

    Critique Paper on Political Change

Related Articles

Case Study on Nissan Motor Company Ltd

Please see attached guidelines and case study. Please respond to section one, Theories and Techniques, and section two, Data Analysis, in the attached. At least one sources must be from...
Read More

An argument in Defense of the Death Penalty Essay Assignment

Hello, I need you to complete my 4 page essay supporting the Death Penalty. As you can see I already completed the first page considering main points and perspectives from...
Read More

Research Paper Assignment on Leader Traits

-The purpose of this assignment is to identify the traits frequently associated with leadership effectiveness and explore the advantages and disadvantages associated with trait approaches to leadership.
Read More

Essay Assignment on Heart Disease Prevention Initiative

Project initiative proposal. In your Assignment, be sure to include the following items:
Read More

Get more from us…

Would you like this sample paper to be sent to your email or would you like to receive weekly articles on how to write your assignments? You can simply send us your request on how to write your paper and we will email you a free guide within 24-36 hours. Kindly subscribe below!

Email Address: support@globalcompose.com